[1] Originally thought of on 19
November 2015, 1:40-1:45am; Expanded 30 November 2015, 8:45-9:15pm PST.
Monday, November 30, 2015
The Logic of Mystery in the Concept of Analogy
“Analogy”
must rise to the transcendental plane of mystery, for if it is reduced to mere
logic then “analogy” as such is destroyed in metaphysical contradiction. This metaphysical
contradiction—“metaphysical” as understood by Aristotelian logical philosophy—is
being and not-being at the same time and in the same respect; it is the union
and intersection of being different and the same, necessarily both at the same time and
in the same respect, since without being the same in the same
respect there could be no commonality between things related by analogy, while
without being different in the same respect there could be no meaningful distinction
between such things. This notion of simultaneously being the same and being distinguished
in the same respect flatly contravenes logic, i.e. the Principle
of Non-Contradition. The only way to save analogy is for it to rise above the
plane of mere logic; analogia must retreat
from logic to inhabit the plane of mysterium.[1]
Saturday, November 7, 2015
Star Wars and the Unfolding of Narrative Art
A certain Star
Wars fan made the following social media remark regarding another Star Wars essay:
"his claim that Episodes I-III are supposed to be seen after Episodes IV-VI…is of course a total nonsense (those films wouldn´t be called Episodes I, II, III, IV, V and VI if that was true)"
I have written the following short essay in
order to show that such claim, while it may be false, is by no means "of
course a total nonsense".
I tried an experiment once: I had a friend who
hadn't ever seen Star Wars and didn't
even know the story (she was truly shocked when she learned that Darth Vader
was Luke's father!). I told her, "I've never done this, but I want to try
it: I want to introduce you to these films in their numerical order, but I'll
skip the end of Star Wars III for a
reason that will become apparent later, and we'll return to that after Star Wars VI.” She agreed.
Well, I had never closely watched these films ‘for
the first time’ since I had actually watched them for the first time, and my
dad showed me the Original Trilogy
(IV, V, & VI) first, then the Prequel
Trilogy (I, II, & III) second. I began to notice many subtle things that are
'assumed' in the Prequel Trilogy that
are already covered in the Original
Trilogy.
For example: In Star Wars II, the understanding of Obi-Wan's Jedi mind trick is
assumed—and it isn't really explained in Star
Wars I, but in Star Wars IV. The
best two examples of all, examples which I think are beyond dispute, are the culturally
ubiquitous "I am your father" of Star
Wars V and the climactic Luke/Leia sibling reveal of Star Wars VI. In Star Wars
III, these two dramatic twists are wrapped into one scene, the Padmé birth
scene, but clearly these were never intended to be revealed in such an
anticlimactic manner; these familiar facts are assumed knowledge during Star Wars III, allowing the birth scene to
serve other purposes in the unfolding of the story.
One of the more subtle examples, but nevertheless
very relevant, would be the music of Star
Wars—all the themes composed by John Williams, and to a lesser extent, by
Kevin Kiner. The “Force theme” appears in Star
Wars IV and is subsequently developed in interesting ways throughout all six
episodes (and The Clone Wars TV
series). Countless themes make important variations throughout the entire saga,
enriching the scenes with subtle meanings that are only fully appreciated when
all previous appearances of such themes and variations have been encountered.
John Williams, like George Lucas, cannot help but develop his compositions only
in the manner in which he actually—outside of the “galaxy far, far away”—composed
his works. The magnificent subtlety of the music of Star Wars, one of the strongest elements of the saga by Lucas’ own
design, can only be fully interpreted and appreciated in the order in which the
themes were actually developed, i.e. the order in which the movies were
actually released.
For the record, I like the Prequel Trilogy far more than the Original Trilogy, so my opinions should not be taken as adding a
movement to the dissonant symphony of Prequel
hate. My opinion regarding the proper order in which to watch the Star Wars movies does not spring from a
belief that the Original Trilogy should be viewed first because it is
better. It is not. I even used to agree with the position that the
movies are best watched in their numerical ordering, which I now do not. I was
never rigid on this matter, and I hope that other fans will give honest
consideration to my argument before rejection or acceptance.
But I do think that it is best to watch the six
episodes (and probably future spinoff ones—including The Force Awakens) in the order in which they
came out from 1977-2005, not in their numerical ordering. Although the internal
chronology is distorted by this, the fact remains that this is the order in
which such films made their appearances in our real world, and a storyteller
cannot help but reveal the unfolding story only in the order in which he actually
makes it known publicly. I think this interpretive theory necessarily applies
to all movie and book series, but it certainly applies to the six original Star Wars movies (and the subsequent Clone Wars series), the coherent corpus
of Lucas' work, The Epic of Anakin as I like to call it.
Originally
published as a social media comment on 9/21/2015. Edited for clarity on
11/7/2015.
The Propriety of Magisterial Authority in Academic Theological Discourse
Originally written 29
November-12 December 2014 as a final paper for Theology 401. I have corrected
typos.
The Magisterium has an
inherent right of judgment in theological discourse, without thereby derogating
from the freedom of the academy.[1]
Academic freedom is not destroyed by the perceived ‘interference’ of
magisterial jurisdiction in academic discourse, for the raison d’ȇtre of the academy is precisely the pursuit and
acquisition of truth, and theological truth properly inheres in and is thereby
under the jurisdiction of the Teaching Authority of the Church, the
Magisterium. This essay will explore the relationship between Magisterial
authority and academic theology and will defend the Ratzingerian thesis by
incorporating the thought of John Paul II and Cardinal Newman concerning
theology, the academy, and the Magisterium.
It
is commonly thought today in the academic establishment—and it seems to me also
in popular culture, or at least among the educated—that ecclesiastical
authority is essentially foreign to the academic enterprise. With the sole
exception of theology, I grant and defend this contention. While every other
academic discipline is aimed essentially at the pursuit and acquisition of
truth, from this it cannot be deduced that the Magisterium has jurisdiction in
all matters of academic discourse.
All disciplines aim at
truth, but not all truth is strictly speaking ‘theological’. Theological truth
is that truth that concerns the Author of all truth, Truth itself. It is often
fallaciously assumed from the divine title “Truth itself” that God is Truth in
an all-encompassing, unqualified, univocal sense. In other words, it is often
deduced from the “Truth itself” title that everything that is truth is a ‘part’
of Truth itself, that the resolution to the problem of the Univocity/Equivocity
of Being is that being is
unequivocally univocal. From this inaccurate deduction it is argued that all
truth falls under the discipline of theology, thereby granting theology the
status of Master Science under which all others are subsumed. As discussed
above, the Magisterium has legitimate jurisdiction in theological matters.
Therefore by this line of argument the Magisterium is granted jurisdiction over
all academic discourse, since academic discourse is related to the truth, God
is Truth, the truth is thereby essentially theological, and the Magisterium has
jurisdiction over theological matters. This position cannot be responsibly
maintained, either from the metaphysical stances regarding Univocity taken by
the Magisterium during the Neoscholastic period, or by the Magisterial
discussion of the proper relationship between faith and reason in St. John Paul
II’s Fides et Ratio. In the thinking
of John Paul, philosophy must remain faithful to its own methods as servant of
the truth, so this precludes an excessive meddling in academic affairs.[2]
However, John Paul also affirms that when philosophy touches upon the subject
of God in its “ancillary” capacity, it thereby falls more directly under the
legitimate jurisdiction of the Magisterium with regard to its truth-claims in a
way similar to theology.[3]
Etymologically,
“Magisterium” derives from magister, teacher.
In the very notion of the Magisterium—the Teaching
Office of the Church—lies the justification for its place in theology. It is
the Church’s divine right to pronounce upon the subject of God and teach others
the divine truths that have been revealed to her.
But the objection of
the contemporary academic establishment—that rational argumentation, and not an
authority external to the academy, should decide upon what is to be taught[4]—does
seem reasonable and bears much weight. Why should “academic theology” exist as
such? Why should theology be considered a science at all, accorded speculative
rights in the academy?
Theology and the
academy were not always together. With the rise of the university in the High
Middle Ages, the proper locus of speculative theology was removed from the
monasteries and monastery schools and transferred to the disputationes and lecture halls of the medieval academy.[5]
Should not theology depart from the house of leaning and return to the house of
prayer, the house of divine learning?
Mystical theology and
other monastic theological traditions should be fostered, restored, treasured,
and spread, but academic theology has its own right of existence, if not for
the sake of itself, then for the sake all other disciplines. According to the
thinking of Newman, theology belongs in the academy both because it is a form
of universal knowledge (his university must teach all universal knowledge) and
because without it the other disciplines would be essentially lacking. For
Newman, every discipline belongs to a “circle of knowledge,”[6]
each one modifying and supplementing the others, so that without any one discipline
the circle would be essentially incomplete.[7]
This is especially the case with theology, he argues, since theology is the
“Science of God”[8]
and its object transcends essentially the methodologies of all other sciences,
at least in certain respects.[9]
Theology complements the philosophical approach of the sciences. As John Paul
teaches, theology helps philosophy grasp truths it would never have grasped,[10]
and also corrects errors which would never have been corrected by mere rational
argumentation.[11]
The argument of Newman defends the rightful place of theology in the academy,
and with this rightful place there comes magisterial jurisdiction over at least
a sphere of academic discourse, i.e. academic theology.
In the last analysis,
every discipline is defined by its methodology, and the methodology of academic
theology necessarily incorporates the Teaching Authority of the Church as one
of its constitutive elements. Magisterial jurisdiction is not foreign to
academic theology; it contributes to its very essence as a discipline, since it
is part of its methodology, its defining element. Academic theology deserves a
place in the academy due to its character as universal knowledge concerning God,
the author and source of all truth, the ultimate object of the academic
enterprise. All truth-seeking leads either to God directly or in a roundabout
way through the truth of metaphysical or material realities. The Magisterium properly
has jurisdiction over theology in the academy, and this does not thereby weaken
its position either as a methodologically-constituted discipline or as an
intellectual endeavor. Rather, the Magisterium aids in the truth-seeking
mission of the academy, the object of all academic pursuits and the object of
academic theology.
[1] J. Ratzinger, “The Nature and Mission of Theology” (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995) 45-46
[1] J. Ratzinger, “The Nature and Mission of Theology” (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995) 45-46
[2] John Paul II, “Fides et Ratio”
(Boston: Pauline Books & Media, 1998) §49
[3] John Paul II, §77
[4] J. Ratzinger, 47
[5] I forget where I read this
historical critique. Please excuse my inability to cite its source properly.
[6] John Henry Newman, “The Idea of
a University” (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2013) 50
[7] Newman, 33-35
[8] Newman, 46
[9] Newman, 38
[10] John Paul II, §101
[11] John Paul II, §51
Friday, November 6, 2015
A Sketch of Love’s Treatment in The Brothers Karamozov
Written
as a 2-hour paper for Humanities 402 on 14 April 2015. I have corrected typos in the
original. The first three paragraphs make simple observations on the role of love, especially eros, in the novel, the fourth paragraph restates Zosima's ethical teaching regarding human love, and the final paragraph makes a genuinely philosophical contribution in the relationship between reason and emotion.
Different kinds of love recur
frequently throughout The Brothers Karamazov. A very common love is romantic
love, a love that seems to affect the plot itself, or to at least add intrigue
and layering to character interaction.
Dimitri and his father Fyodor both
fall in love with Grushenka. Both men seem not so much to want to love her and
give their lives to her service so much as to defeat the other in competition
and possess her as the object of their eros.
Later, after his father is
murdered, Dimitri tries to gain the hand of his beloved. He finds out that she
is involved with a Polish officer and is heartily disheartened. In the course
of the evening, however, the Polish chap proves himself to be far more
possessive than Dimitri ever was; it can be doubted whether the Polish man ever
loved Grushenka, since he does not seem to care for her subtle feelings and
openly insults Russia. At this point Dimitri proves that he does love her,
truly, and that he wants what is best for her. It should be noted that he
definitely thinks that what is best for her is to marry him, it still seems
primarily motivated by true eros and
not a perversion of erotic love.
Zosima exhorts his brethren to love
everything, the trees, leaves, children, animals—everything. He teaches that
everyone can love occasionally, even evil people. This statement seems
surprising at first, but Jesus confirms this by saying ‘if you who are evil
know how to do good to your children, how much more will you Heavenly Father
take care of you?’. God loves all things all the time, since God is Love. Human
persons, however, have trouble loving all the time. Zosima, therefore, urges
his followers—and us—to strive to love all things at all times, since if all
our energy is being spent on love than none can be spent on hatred.
The narrator provides a curious
reference to love in the context of people jeering at Zosima and Alyosha’s
reaction. Alyosha even questions why God has not vindicated his humble servant
and made the holiness of Zosima apparent to all. The narrator recounts that he
is glad that love gains the upper hand over reason in this instance, since a
reasonable man will always come back to reason, but there are times when love
must overrule reason. The narrator seems to create a divide between love and
reason, at least certain types of love and reason. For Christians this is
impossible in the strict sense, since God is Love and God is Logos. However, in
a more general way, could this be possible? What does this divide mean? I think
the narrator—and maybe the ‘author’—is trying to show us the limits of the
“narrow Euclidian mind” that he wrote about. There are times when a certain
kind of reasoning, formed by the strict application of logic to actions and
events without any consultation, advice, or influence of emotions, is
inappropriate. There are certain times when feelings trump reasonings. This is
what Dostoevsky is showing us, that mere reason, reductionistic reason, Enlightenment reason is not the absolute
indicator of propriety vis-à-vis
reality. The emotions—strictly speaking ‘non-rational’ in themselves—must be
consulted in making rational judgments and in taking action. Dostoevsky does
not place a strict dichotomy between reason and love. He shows that love, not
merely an emotion but certainly with emotional power, can sometimes overrule
the “narrow Euclidian mind”. Sometimes it should. Sometimes it must.
Wednesday, October 7, 2015
Descartes' Restoration of Philosophical Methodology
This is probably my favorite short
paper I wrote during college. It perfectly articulates my philosophy vis-à-vis the Neoscholastic
establishment viewpoint—that Descartes caused the downfall of philosophy, and
that Aristotle should be restored and Descartes suppressed by the authority of
the academy—by arguing that Descartes was a true philosopher, restored
philosophy, and that no true philosophy can “ruin” philosophy, while a
tyrannically enforced false philosophy most certainly can.
It was written in Humanities 401
on 18 November 2014, as an expansion of the paper from 9 September 2014,
with some elements incorporated from the paper of 13 October 2014. I have made
slight revisions.
Has
Descartes helped or hindered philosophy? Evaluate.
Descartes
has made a positive contribution to the philosophical enterprise. He asks
questions that did not even seem to occur to the ancient or scholastic
philosophers, and in so doing demonstrates his brilliant originality of
thought. Any time valid questions are posed and arguments given it cannot be
held that philosophy is ruined, for that is precisely what philosophy is, the
posing and answering of questions and the response or refutation of such
answers in a constant journey of the human intellect. The unabashed search for
truth which philosophy is demands such honest inquiry, free from the
impositions and constraints of a systematized fundamental world view.
Descartes
sought to transcend these systematic constraints. In his commentary on the Meditations,
Descartes states that no one has ever seriously doubted that he exists, that
he has a body, and that other material things exist. Descartes simply wonders
if it is possible to prove the existence of these things without relying upon
the accuracy of the senses. Actual doubt is improperly attributed to
Descartes, when he really was engaging in systematic doubt; he never
actually doubted the things which he was ‘doubting’ in his thought experiment.
He was simply raising a novel question: whether the things we commonly
apprehend though the senses can be known without the use and accuracy of the
senses.
This
was an honest intellectual and philosophical inquiry which the academic
establishment of his day—and the establishment of the contemporary
Neoscholastic Catholic college—condemns as a fruitless and disordered departure
from the ways of Aristotelian epistemology. Descartes should be commended for
preserving the integrity of the philosophic enterprise, for a philosophy that
simply hands down by the authority of the academy and the ancients ‘perennial
truths’ somehow placed above the realm of disputation is not properly called
“philosophy” so much as a common belief system akin to faith.
As
J. Ratzinger distinguishes in Introduction to Christianity, faith comes
from a community and the authority and loving trust thereof, whereas philosophy
is born of the lone philosopher and its true understanding is based upon an
evaluation of the arguments advanced in defense thereof. Philosophy is
essentially disputative, and the authenticity of the philosophic enterprise is
dependent upon an impartial search for truth. The element of ‘the teacher’ and
‘the taught’ dicens stricte destroys this authentic and disputative
search by replacing it with ‘facts’ passed on by authority. Philosophy is
reduced at best to a history of what has been thought or to a common credo of
the true, and at worst to a dogmatism or quasi-ideology, an ‘ism’ which can
explain everything by deduction from a single premise (cf. H. Arendt)—that
Aristotelian modes of thinking are always correct. Descartes preserves the
integrity of philosophy in his thought by preserving the integrity of properly
philosophic methodology. He serves as a great reminder that cultural and
historical assumptions should not limit the heights of philosophic discovery.
It
is granted that Descartes began the downfall of the supremacy and unquestioned
legitimacy of the ancient philosophy and the Scholasticism which had been built
upon it—a systemic doubt caused by systematic doubt, as it
were.[1] But the need to save a system or
founding principle of a system, e.g. “All knowledge begins with the senses,”
should never necessitate the dismissal of novel modes of inquiry. If a question
is posed and a response is given, it does not serve the pursuit of truth merely
to dismiss it based upon the principles of one’s own system. Rather the
response should be addressed directly within the metaphysical framework in
which the question arose. The historical result of Cartesian thought was the
decline of the unquestioned dominance of Aristotelian, and consequently
Thomistic, modes of thinking, but by so doing Cartesianism has restored
philosophy to its proper methodological integrity, and Descartes has thereby
helped philosophy. He has done this not by displacing Ancient or Scholastic
thought—which are properly philosophic in themselves and deserve an equal place
in dialogue with post-Cartesian modern philosophy—but by transcending the
tyranny of prescribed modes of thought and thereby restoring the truly
philosophic endeavor. Descartes gave to philosophy an entirely new way of
viewing reality by following the rigorous and fearless methodology of
truth-seeking, and the necessary fruits of such effort can never ruin
philosophy. Only dogmatic insistence upon established modes of thought, for no
other reason than the authority of the ages, ruins philosophy.
[1] I added “—a systemic doubt caused by systematic
doubt, as it were.” on 7 October 2015, 7:25pm PST.
Sunday, September 6, 2015
"Original Instruments"
Last night I wanted to relax and read. I
decided I wanted to listen to woodland bird sounds. I had my windows open, so
the sound of peepers was very loud. I really didn’t want to hear them
anymore, so I put on some bird sounds.
Then I realized something, something
that I have been thinking about in relation to music recordings vs. live music:
these frogs, crickets, and owls were singing to me; God has inscribed in their
natures specific parts to play in the symphony of nature; the entire production
was for my benefit as human person, the pinnacle of physical creation.
I would not listen to an mp3 of a classical piece if I were at a classical concert. Why would I listen to a pre-recorded nature when I had a front-row seat to the most splendid concert in the universe, with God my Creator conducting?
The symphony of nature is the composition of the Creator; maybe next time I want to “relax” to artificial reproductions of nature, I should listen to the magnificence of live performance on the ‘original instruments’, the actual creatures for which the natural symphony was composed.
Spring Peeper |
I would not listen to an mp3 of a classical piece if I were at a classical concert. Why would I listen to a pre-recorded nature when I had a front-row seat to the most splendid concert in the universe, with God my Creator conducting?
The symphony of nature is the composition of the Creator; maybe next time I want to “relax” to artificial reproductions of nature, I should listen to the magnificence of live performance on the ‘original instruments’, the actual creatures for which the natural symphony was composed.
Thursday, August 20, 2015
Reflections on Academia and Philosophical Methodology
There are many issues with contemporary academia; most
scholars seem to acknowledge this, although their particular opinions on the
issues and causes vary as much as Justice Kennedy’s opinions on the U.S. Supreme
Court. I’ve been thinking about academia alot[1]
lately; as a person who fancies himself a philosopher, and as a recent BA
graduate, I have been thinking about the nature and interrelation of things
such as “academia”, “the intellectual life”, and “philosophy”. Academia seems
to maintain it has a monopoly upon the practice, or “profession” and “teaching”,
of philosophy. But can “philosophy” really be a day-job? Can “philosophy”
really be taught? Or does the nature of teaching philosophy actually corrupt
the very nature of what is claimed to be transmitted? In other words, are the
phrases “professor of philosophy”, “teacher of philosophy”, and “student of philosophy”
actually contradictions in terms? Can “philosophy” be transmitted from teacher
to student, or must it be practiced individually by the philosopher? What is
the nature of that which is being
transmitted from teacher to student, and is it true philosophy, or merely the
faint resemblance of true philosophy, the outer appearance of true philosophy
obscuring the essential corruption wrought by positivistic historical
commentators?
Well if you cannot tell my answer to those questions, then
you may need to take rhetoric lessons before you pursue authentic philosophy.
In short, I think that philosophy cannot be taught or transmitted, that the
very act of transmission properly
understood corrupts the nature of the philosophical method, and that to
understand philosophy, one must be a philosopher himself, one who analyzes the
arguments of others in a dialectic of honesty in pursuit of truth. Such a
methodology precludes “teaching” and necessitates active participation—“philosophizing”.
Philosophy can only be philosophized among philosophers; it cannot be
transmitted from teacher to student in an allegedly “philosophical” tradition,
for such a tradition necessarily precludes authentic philosophy. Philosophy is
better understood as a verb than a noun; the notion of “teaching” philosophy relies
on the concept of philosophy as a positive corpus of thought produced by
notable thinkers which can be dissected and fed to malleable students often
incapably of true philosophy. Such academic passivity precludes philosophical
activity.
The academy presses scholars by capitalist production to “produce”
intellectual fruit through rigorous publishing requirements, which strangle
genuine insight—that which must wait for the whim of the intellectus. Therefore academia is doomed to be positivist &
merely historically descriptive, which has lead to its irrelevance and to the distortion
of philosophy and the corruption of the very thinkers’ methodology.
Intellectual ideologies such as Radical Feminism and Neo-Thomism
are not based on intellectus or ratio, but on anger and on the desire
for bringing about a radical new world which they have envisioned as ideal, not
so much as a result of their philosophy but as a goal towards which quasi-argumentative
constructs which they would consider “philosophy” have been formulated. Since
their conclusions have been preformulated, these “scholars” must conform
reality and the free dialectic of truth to their narrow path toward their pre-ordained
esoteric revelations. These movements (insofar as they can be classified as
coherent “movements”) are not based on the quiet contemplation and intellectual
activity of the truly philosophical life, but are falsifications of honest
dialectics and are thereby disbarred from the category of authentic philosophy.
[1] I firmly hold that “alot”
is a true word, due to continuous popular usage and the nature of verbal
contraction as proven time and again with words such as “to-day”. I have
accordingly chosen to revert my autocorrect.
Friday, July 10, 2015
In Defense of Marginalia
I have a delightfully diverse collection of old books; I acquired many discarded editions from my college library (my oldest item, a collection of Hindu sacred texts, dates to 1891). Some are in excellent shape, others not so much. But I am privileged to have a fairly large collection of fairly rare volumes.
I keep many on my large bookshelf so that when whim strikes I can take one off and browse for a while. (When I'm busy, they serve to taunt me and my work-a-day life). Today I picked up "The Art of Enjoying Art" by A. Philip McMahon (New York: Whittlesey House, 1938), a thorough volume on art appreciation and theory. But what struck me was a charmingly antediluvian Ex Libris tag on the inside front cover. It reads:
I keep many on my large bookshelf so that when whim strikes I can take one off and browse for a while. (When I'm busy, they serve to taunt me and my work-a-day life). Today I picked up "The Art of Enjoying Art" by A. Philip McMahon (New York: Whittlesey House, 1938), a thorough volume on art appreciation and theory. But what struck me was a charmingly antediluvian Ex Libris tag on the inside front cover. It reads:
WHEN YOU USE A BOOK
Are you careful with it?
Do you try to keep it clean?
Do you refrain from writing or marking it?
Do you resist the temptation to roll up the corners of the pages and tear out little nips?
If so, good.
If not, try to think of books as human beings with feelings just like yours. And resolve today to treat books as friends.
While tearing out little nips constitutes a crime against posterity, the insinuation that marking or writing in a book constitutes abuse and a devaluing of the book's "human" dignity is flatly false. Let us for a moment take to heart what the last point commands: "try to think of books as human beings with feelings just like yours...[and] treat books as friends."
How many of you have friends that you merely observe or visually read? Now I'm not talking about "Facebook friends". I"m talking about real, deep, close friends; even best friends. Would you just stand in front of them for hours, awkwardly staring in silence? Or would you enter into a varyingly diverse dialogue of jocularity and empathy? Writing and marking in books serves as a quasi-dialogic exercise between reader and codex. While the book qua codex is unable to speak, the book qua vehicle of human intellection enters into dialogue with the reader on a deeply personal level, if only the reader accepts the invitation to listen, for without listening no dialogue can exist. In the words of Joseph Ratzinger ("The Nature and Mission of Theology" [San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1995], pp. 32-33):
[D]ialogue does not take place simply because people are talking. Mere talk is the deterioration of dialogue that occurs when there has been a failure to reach it. Dialogue first comes into being where there is not only speech but also listening. Moreover, such listening must be the medium of an encounter; this encounter is the condition of an inner contact which leads to mutual comprehension. Reciprocal understanding, finally, deepens and transforms the being of the interlocutors.
The physical constitution of the codex receives the thoughts and ruminations of the attentive reader. Marginalia—book markings worthy of the name—form a dialogue with future generations as well, linking the living with the dead in a communion of thought. The reader thereby enters into a dialogue with the substance of the author's thought, a dialogue that transcends space and time, a metaphysical dialogue expressed through humble scribbles, a meeting of the physical and the metaphysical, of time and eternal truth.
Marginalia do not derogate from the inherent worth of the book anymore than tattoos derogate from the inherent dignity of the human person, body and soul. While they may detract from the value of the book [unless they are of some antiquity], if this is of concern to the private owner (in contrast to the library patron) then the owner is already treating his book not as a human being or friend with feelings, but as a slave, an intelligent subject acquired and sold for monetary gain.
I'm not seriously asserting that slavery exists in such framework, but if the goal is to treat books as human beings then they should not be expected to stay in mint condition until they can be sold. We should engage with them as objects of intelligence, and for many, marginalia serve as a means of dialogic encounter.
Marginalia do not derogate from the inherent worth of the book anymore than tattoos derogate from the inherent dignity of the human person, body and soul. While they may detract from the value of the book [unless they are of some antiquity], if this is of concern to the private owner (in contrast to the library patron) then the owner is already treating his book not as a human being or friend with feelings, but as a slave, an intelligent subject acquired and sold for monetary gain.
I'm not seriously asserting that slavery exists in such framework, but if the goal is to treat books as human beings then they should not be expected to stay in mint condition until they can be sold. We should engage with them as objects of intelligence, and for many, marginalia serve as a means of dialogic encounter.
Friday, June 26, 2015
Digital Minimalism
I'm consolidating my blogs, so these are my posted artworks from my former blog Digital Minimalism, circa 24 June 2013. I am particularly proud of my IV Seasons set, especially the stark contrast in Winter, although the Allegory of Consumerism is an old classic. I hope that you enjoy my art and my style, and feel free to comment!
Allegory of Consumerism
IV Seasons
Spring
Summer
Fall
Winter
Monday, June 15, 2015
Rain on My Parade
Today was rainy. I went outside thinking what a crappy day it was, but taking a second look, and remembering the writings of Luther Standing Bear on the Lakota view of all weather as a gift of Wakan Tanka, I realized how beautiful the rain-soaked nature really was. Why do we generally despise non-sunny days? Why is "bad weather" even a phrase?
I imagine that regarding rain in particular, we personalize and emotionalize it, viewing it analogically as gloomy tears covering the earth. Why should we view rain this way? Would it not be more healthy, not to mention more hydrospherically accurate, to view rainy days as the life-giving vibrancy of nature?
I imagine that regarding rain in particular, we personalize and emotionalize it, viewing it analogically as gloomy tears covering the earth. Why should we view rain this way? Would it not be more healthy, not to mention more hydrospherically accurate, to view rainy days as the life-giving vibrancy of nature?
The Journey Begins
This blog is about living the philosophical life, a life worth living. While we might discuss complex issues or philosophic subtleties, this blog will encompass more than merely academic philosophy, often a philosophy cut off from real inquiry into the nature of the True—a sterile, academic pseudo-philosophy which I have attempted to overcome in the philosophy of law at my blog Beatific Juridical Teleology.
This blog will have a broader scope; that is all I have to say. The philosophical life is not to be planned but to be lived. I hope that Philosophical Living serves both author and reader in living lives ordered to the pursuit of truth in a dialectic of honesty. But leave your ideology boots at the door; the house of truth is easily soiled.
This blog will have a broader scope; that is all I have to say. The philosophical life is not to be planned but to be lived. I hope that Philosophical Living serves both author and reader in living lives ordered to the pursuit of truth in a dialectic of honesty. But leave your ideology boots at the door; the house of truth is easily soiled.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)